Epistemic virtue

The epistemic virtues, as identified by virtue epistemologists, reflect their contention that belief is an ethical process, and thus susceptible to the intellectual virtue or vice of one's own life and personal experiences. Some epistemic virtues have been identified by W. Jay Wood, based on research into the medieval tradition.

Overview

Being an epistemically virtuous person is often equated with being a critical thinker.[1]

Epistemic virtues include conscientiousness.[2]

These can be contrasted to the epistemic vices such as:

Note that in this context curiosity bears the medieval connotation of attraction to unwholesome things, in contrast to the positive studious (or perhaps inquisitive).

See also

Notes

  1. Bishop, M., & Trout, J. D. 2004. Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  2. Greco, John. 2011. Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Virtue Epistemology". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. .

References

  • W. Jay Wood, Epistemology: Becoming Intellectually Virtuous (InterVarsity Press, 1998)
  • Robert C. Roberts and W. Jay Wood, Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology (Oxford University Press, 2007)
  • Linda Zagzebski, Virtues of the Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1996)
  • Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebski, eds. Intellectual Virtue (Oxford University Press, 2003)
  • Greco, John. "Virtue Epistemology". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Epistemic virtue at PhilPapers
  • "Epistemic virtue". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Virtue Epistemology at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • Epistemic akrasia (irrationality) as a deficit of virtue by Christopher Hookway
  • Is Inclusion an Epistemic Virtue? by Harvey Siegel
  • Review of James Montmarquet's Epistemic Virtue and Doxastic Responsibility by Jonathan L. Kvanvig
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.